This fall the political bombast
between candidates has grown loud, aggressive, and personal.
Candidates are no longer satisfied with slinging mud on their rivals
in campaign ads; they are using televised debates to call each other
“liar” to their faces. As a rhetorical theorist, the first thing
I would like to point out this week is that there is an important
difference between a) scoring political points with an audience
because one has belittled an opponent with a personal attack and b)
scoring political points with an audience because one has offered a
substantive claim to dispute what the other has said.
Rhetoricians use the word “fallacy”
to refer to any bad argument that scores points with uncritical
audience members. Merely calling someone a name doesn't prove
anything, and we refer to the “fallacy of name calling” by its
latin name “ad hominem.” While personal attacks may offer the
impression that candidates are willing to stand up to others for what
they believe in, they also demonstrate that candidates are willing to
employ irrational and unethical methods to achieve whatever political
results they hope to gain.
It is certainly difficult to maintain
a civil and reasonable discourse when someone is standing on a
platform a few feet away and making personal attacks rather than
asking for the reasoning behind policies. This type of
testosterone-fueled political bullying is nothing new of course.
Back in 1912, William Howard Taft and Theodore Roosevelt were both
vying for the nomination to be the Republican candidate in that
year’s presidential election, and the dispute between the two
former friends grew heated and personal. At one point, in a live
debate in a Chicago convention hall, the increasing animosity between
the two led both candidates to resort to gutter-level, no-class,
gob-in-the- spittoon name-calling. Crossing the line from political
discourse into personal attack, Roosevelt called Taft a “puzzlewit.”
Taft responded by calling Roosevelt a “honeyfugler.” A
puzzlewit, by the way, is person who is puzzled by life, which
is to say, a stupid person. A honeyfugler is basically a
swindling liar who gets what he wants by duping people into believing
his frauds. So there you go; it's a hundred years later and the
voters are still trying to decide whether to vote for the puzzlewit
or the honeyfugler. Personally, I will vote for an honest puzzlewit
over an astute honeyfugler every time, but you have to make up your
own mind when you draw the curtain to the voting booth.
Ad hominem is almost always the first
attack of bullies. When their victims respond to their name calling,
bullies use their victims' response as justification for whatever
violence (threatened or concrete) they introduce afterwards. As a
child, I was often the victim of bullying, and that is why as an
adult I am so passionate about the ideals of rhetoric.
Authentic rhetoric respects the agency of others and expects
relevant truth to be in and of itself persuasive; authentic
rhetorical debate is antithetical to violence. Authentic
rhetoric maintains that honest persuasion must be free of coercion.
If there is a single principle that informs my thinking as a
rhetorical theorist it is this: While a threat may provide us with
a good motivation to act, a threat never offers a good reason to
believe.
When I was a kid on the playground in
elementary school, bullies used to knock down smaller children (such
as myself), sit on the their chests, and smack them in the face until
their victims said something to satisfy the bullies' need to have
their dominance acknowledged. “Say 'I'm great' if you want me to
let you up,” the bullies would say while smacking me in the face.
“Okay, you're great,” I would tell them, “Now get off of me.”
This is without question the single most important lesson I learned
in elementary school: Just because a bully can force you to say
he's great while he's smacking you in the face, it doesn't mean the
bully is really a great person. Decades later, as an adult, I
can now vocalize what I only understood then: Coercion does not offer
any reason for belief. Violence can only offer a motivation to
act; violence cannot offer a reason to believe.
Imagine you are attacked by a mugger
who points a gun at you and says, “Give me your money or I will
shoot you.” The threat of being shot offers a legitimate
motivation to give the mugger your money (because obviously your
money is not worth much if you are too dead to spend it). Now
imagine the same mugger with the gun saying this instead, “Believe
that I deserve the money in your wallet more than you do or I will
shoot you.” Clearly, just because he can shoot you, the mugger has
not offered you any relevant reason to believe he deserves your
money. Even if the mugger says, “I need you to say that I deserve
your money more than you do or I will shoot you,” the mugger has
merely given you a good motive to say what he wants to hear, but he
has not given you a relevant reason to believe he deserves your
money. The threat of physical violence can compel people to act, but
clearly, a threat of physical violence is only relevant to the belief
in the threat. If the mugger says, “See this gun? Then believe me
when I tell you that I will shoot you if you do not give me your
money.” In this instance, the threat of being shot is relevant to
the belief in getting shot, but notice how absurd it is to believe
the mugger if he decides to start tacking things on to his threat,
“Believe that I will shoot you and that I'm also a decent human
being.” The gun not only does not support his additional claim
that he is a decent person, but it entirely negates it.
The idea that people should not base
their beliefs upon threats (or rewards for that matter) is what I
call “Unicorn Theory.” It simply goes like this: if you neighbor
claims he saw a unicorn, you wouldn't believe him merely because he
threatened to shoot you if said you disbelieved him. While the
threat of being shot is a good motive to tell your neighbor
you believe in his unicorn, it is not a relevant reason to
believe he actually saw a unicorn. If he offers you a suitcase of
money to say you believe in his unicorn, he has again given you a
good motive to say you believe in his unicorn, but a good
motive to say something is simply not the same as a good reason
to believe something.
This leads me to another of my
rhetorical theories that I will now present to you, the reader, in
the form of a puzzle. I call this “Dudding's Conundrum.” If you
have an answer for my puzzle, I would love to hear it. I could not
be more sincere in saying that this mystery has been my life's
challenge; it is my own personal “Holy Grail.” Thinking about
this is where my brain goes when it has nothing else to think about.
I don't know if this puzzle has an answer (or at least an answer that
I can comprehend) but if you think you have an answer, I will make a
genuine effort to consider what you have to say.
So here goes: I am an agnostic. Now the word
agnostic is used in a lot different ways by many different
people so what I mean by agnostic is that I think God is
unknowable or, at least, incomprehensible. I'm not sure what I know
about God, but what I know about me is that my brain does not
function in a way that makes religion comprehensible. I am a
religious dyslexic. What apparently makes sense to other
people about God simply does not make sense to me. In light of that,
Dudding's Conundrum is this:
“Would a moral and rational God authorize agents to speak on His
behalf and then allow them to use immoral or irrational arguments?”
Here's
my argument as an analogy. (Do whatever you can to pull it part, but
remember, you'll score no points by merely calling me names.)
Suppose you are working as a cashier at a cash register, and part of
your job is to make sure all the transactions you handle in the
course of a day are legitimate. Now imagine that someone has come in
and wants to make a large purchase using a corporate credit card.
For whatever reason, you begin to wonder if the person holding the
card is really authorized to use it. “Are you authorized to use
this card?” you might ask the purchaser.
“There's
unlimited funds tied to that card,” the purchaser responds.
“Yes,”
you say, “I ran the card and there is no limit on the funds
available, but how is that relevant to your authorization to use the
card?”
“Look,”
the cardholder says, “you make commissions on your sales, right?
Then wouldn't it be to your advantage to just believe I can use the
card? This sale would mean a huge windfall to you.”
“Yes,
if it's a legitimate transaction then I stand to gain a lot here, but
a financial bribe is not a good reason to believe that you have
authority to use the card.”
“What
if I offered to buy you anything you want in this store with this
card if you are just willing to accept that I am an authorized user?”
“Then,
I would say that the bribe makes it much less likely that you are an
authorized user of the corporate card. I can't imagine that this
corporation would authorize users who offer bribes. Bribes are
unethical.”
“What
if I said I was going to use the funds on this card to hire some
thugs to beat you up in the parking lot after you get off work?”
“I
would say that the threat of violence also makes your claim to be a
legitimate authorized user more dubious because I can't imagine an
ethical company giving authorization to people to use their credit if
they are the type of people to issue irrelevant threats.”
So,
what has this to do with religion? Everything. The basic argument of "revealed religion" is that God has authorized spokesmen (call them
prophets) to speak on His behalf, and they all use the threats of
hell or the bribe of heaven as an induce to believe they are indeed
God's agent on earth. Hence, Dudding's Conundrum:
“Would a moral and rational God authorize agents to speak on His
behalf and allow them to use immoral or irrational arguments?”
I
sincerely look forward to rational responses to this post. Keep thinking rhetorically, and I'll be back next week.
I don't believe that a moral and rational God would authorize agents to speak on His/Her/Its behalf, nor allow them to use immoral or irrational arguments. That said, it doesn't stop people from appointing themselves as "authorized agents" and spewing immoral, irrational, and often hate-mongering arguments.
ReplyDeleteRegardless of denomination, it seems that churches - especially here in America - rely on semantical arguments & construct a morality based upon what they want their respective holy books to read rather than promoting the central tenents of the books themselves. Most of my daily interactions put me in touch with people who give me a *motive* to let them believe that we hold the same value/religious system, but never a *reason* to actually do so. (I prefer my conversations to include more fact than fear-mongering, so I'm entirely out of place.)
This whole topic is assuming that God is moral and rational in a way that we can comprehend. I believe that the Creator of the universe is in no way small enough to fully grasp in any human way. I can't fathom a Creator that is minimized to our current society's obsession with duality, gender definitions, and limitations. We can touch upon truths and sometimes catch a glimpse of the unknown, but I don't personally have any desire to have a list of what God "wants" me to believe or do from some "agent" who is just as flawed as myself.
Wow, Crystal, thanks for the response. Clearly, you get the argument I'm making. As an agnostic, I don't know if God exists, but I have hope if She (He or It) does exist, that the odds are She's far more wiser and compassionate than I am. I'm not willing to speculate beyond that. My brain is too small and wired the wrong way "to get" mainstream religion.
DeleteI would echo some of what Crystal said. I also want to push back on your statement: "and they all use the threats of hell or the bribe of heaven as an induce to believe they are indeed God's agent on earth."
ReplyDeleteFirst, I get the feeling that you're mostly talking about Christianity here, considering it is the religion that most refers to these two supernatural locations. There are far more religions out there that speak of an afterlife of some sort, but it is not necessarily heaven or hell, per se. I don't know enough to speak for religions other than my own, but I would say that representatives of these religions might not agree with your statement.
Second, if we are talking about Christianity, certainly *all* of us do not use threats or bribes to convince people to believe what we believe. I understand that you are probably not necessarily trying to imply that all theologians and spiritual leaders in the church are cut from the same cloth, but as a rhetorician, you of all people know that you have to choose what you write carefully. ;-)
Here's my own ideas: I *think* I believe in heaven. I'm not sure what I think of hell. I do know that traditionally, the "kingdom of God" has been understood to mean "heaven/that celestial place where God is." This is problematic to me for a number of reasons. As far as evangelizing through threats or promises goes, this is entirely ineffective, as you have argued. Not only can no person force another to believe anything, but if this is how we go about it, why on earth would you want to join up?
Thanks, Rachel, for your response. I think you are right to "push back" against the generalization that "all prophets use threats and bribes" to establish and secure their credibility. At the same time, while as an agnostic I regard God as unfathomable, the arch of my perplexity remains the mystery of whether a rational and moral God would authorize his representatives to use irrational or immoral arguments to share "His" messages. If God's omniscience makes my understanding minuscule (I have only had this singular life experience to come to this understanding that coercion has no place in establishing belief), then why in the process of speaking to prophets wouldn't He had told them, "Hey making threats will give people legitimate reason to think you are frauds so don't do that"? Furthermore, if God is omnipotent, why would He rely on prophets at all? Wouldn't direct communication with each of us be more effective than using middlemen who use arguments that erode their own credibility? I am sincerely perplexed that the claim every prophet makes (that God told me something He wants me to share with the rest of you) isn't regarded as even more suspect as the neighbor's claim that he saw a unicorn.
DeleteThanks for staying my friend, Rachel. It's nice to be able to pose these questions to a real theologian; I am just an amateur. I hope you know I respect your opinion even when I am incapable of understanding it. I was raised in the same denomination you attend. I basically left the church because I was made unwelcome for raising these types of questions.